Logical framework explained
In logic, a logical framework provides a means to define (or present) a logic as a signature in a higher-order type theory in such a way that provability of a formula in the original logic reduces to a type inhabitation problem in the framework type theory.[1] [2] This approach has been used successfully for (interactive) automated theorem proving. The first logical framework was Automath; however, the name of the idea comes from the more widely known Edinburgh Logical Framework, LF. Several more recent proof tools like Isabelle are based on this idea.[1] Unlike a direct embedding, the logical framework approach allows many logics to be embedded in the same type system.[3]
Overview
A logical framework is based on a general treatment of syntax, rules and proofs by means of a dependently typed lambda calculus. Syntax is treated in a style similar to, but more general than Per Martin-Löf's system of arities.
To describe a logical framework, one must provide the following:
- A characterization of the class of object-logics to be represented;
- An appropriate meta-language;
- A characterization of the mechanism by which object-logics are represented.
This is summarized by:
"Framework = Language + Representation."
LF
In the case of the LF logical framework, the meta-language is the λΠ-calculus. This is a system of first-order dependent function types which are related by the propositions as types principle to first-order minimal logic. The key features of the λΠ-calculus are that it consists of entities of three levels: objects, types and kinds (or type classes, or families of types). It is predicative, all well-typed terms are strongly normalizing and Church-Rosser and the property of being well-typed is decidable. However, type inference is undecidable.
A logic is represented in the LF logical framework by the judgements-as-types representation mechanism. This is inspired by Per Martin-Löf's development of Kant's notion of judgement, in the 1983 Siena Lectures. The two higher-order judgements, the hypothetical
and the general,
, correspond to the ordinary and dependent function space, respectively. The methodology of judgements-as-types is that judgements are represented as the types of their proofs. A logical system
is represented by its signature which assigns kinds and types to a finite set of constants that represents its syntax, its judgements and its rule schemes. An object-logic's rules and proofs are seen as primitive proofs of hypothetico-general judgements
.
An implementation of the LF logical framework is provided by the Twelf system at Carnegie Mellon University. Twelf includes
- a logic programming engine
- meta-theoretic reasoning about logic programs (termination, coverage, etc.)
- an inductive meta-logical theorem prover
See also
Further reading
- Book: Helmut Schwichtenberg, Ralf Steinbrüggen. Proof and system-reliability. Logical frameworks – a brief introduction. 2002. . 978-1-4020-0608-1. Frank Pfenning.
- Robert Harper, Furio Honsell and Gordon Plotkin. A Framework For Defining Logics. Journal of the Association for Computing Machinery, 40(1):143-184, 1993.
- Arnon Avron, Furio Honsell, Ian Mason and Randy Pollack. Using typed lambda calculus to implement formal systems on a machine. Journal of Automated Reasoning, 9:309-354, 1992.
- Robert Harper. An Equational Formulation of LF. Technical Report, University of Edinburgh, 1988. LFCS report ECS-LFCS-88-67.
- Robert Harper, Donald Sannella and Andrzej Tarlecki. Structured Theory Presentations and Logic Representations. Annals of Pure and Applied Logic, 67(1-3):113-160, 1994.
- Samin Ishtiaq and David Pym. A Relevant Analysis of Natural Deduction. Journal of Logic and Computation 8, 809-838, 1998.
- Samin Ishtiaq and David Pym. Kripke Resource Models of a Dependently-typed, Bunched
-calculus
. Journal of Logic and Computation 12(6), 1061-1104, 2002.
-calculus
. Studia Logica 54: 199-230, 1995.
-calculus
. In: G. Huet and G. Plotkin (eds), Logical Frameworks, Cambridge University Press, 1991. - Didier Galmiche and David Pym. Proof-search in type-theoretic languages:an introduction. Theoretical Computer Science 232 (2000) 5-53.
- Philippa Gardner. Representing Logics in Type Theory. Technical Report, University of Edinburgh, 1992. LFCS report ECS-LFCS-92-227.
- Gilles Dowek. The undecidability of typability in the lambda-pi-calculus. In M. Bezem, J.F. Groote (Eds.), Typed Lambda Calculi and Applications. Volume 664 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 139-145, 1993.
- David Pym. Proofs, Search and Computation in General Logic. Ph.D. thesis, University of Edinburgh, 1990.
- David Pym. A Unification Algorithm for the
-calculus.
International Journal of Foundations of Computer Science 3(3), 333-378, 1992.External links
Notes and References
- Book: Bart Jacobs. Categorical Logic and Type Theory. 2001. Elsevier. 978-0-444-50853-9. 598.
- Book: Dov M. Gabbay. What is a logical system?. 1994. Clarendon Press. 978-0-19-853859-2. 382.
- Book: Ana Bove. Luis Soares Barbosa. Alberto Pardo. Language Engineering and Rigorous Software Development: International LerNet ALFA Summer School 2008, Piriapolis, Uruguay, February 24 - March 1, 2008, Revised, Selected Papers. 2009. Springer. 978-3-642-03152-6. 48.