In linguistics, a small clause consists of a subject and its predicate, but lacks an overt expression of tense.[1] Small clauses have the semantic subject-predicate characteristics of a clause, and have some, but not all, properties of a constituent. Structural analyses of small clauses vary according to whether a flat or layered analysis is pursued. The small clause is related to the phenomena of raising-to-object, exceptional case-marking, accusativus cum infinitivo, and object control.
The two main analyses of small clauses originate with Edwin Williams (1975, 1980) and Tim Stowell (1981). Williams' analysis follows the Theory of Predication, where the "subject" is the "external argument of a maximal projection". In contrast, Stowell's theory follows the Theory of Small Clauses, supported by linguists such as Chomsky, Aarts, and Kitagawa.[2] This theory uses X-bar theory to treat small clauses as constituents. Linguists debate which analysis to pursue, as there is evidence for both sides of the debate.
The term "small clause" was coined by Edwin Williams in 1975, who specifically looked at "reduced relatives, adverbial modifier phrases, and gerundive phrases".[3] The following three examples are treated in Williams' 1975 paper as "small clauses", as cited in Balazs 2012. However, not all linguists consider these to be small clauses according to the term's modern definition.
The modern definition of a small clause is an [NP XP] in a predicative relationship. This definition was proposed by Edwin Williams in 1980, who introduced the concept of Predication.[4] He proposed that the subject NP and the predicate XP are related via co-indexation, which is made possible by c-command. In Williams' analysis, the [NP XP] of a small clause does not form a constituent.[5]
Timothy Stowell in 1981 analyzed the small clause as a constituent,[6] and proposed a structure using X-bar theory. Stowell proposes that the subject is defined as an NP occurring in a specifier position, that case is assigned in the specifier position, and that not all categories have subjects.[7] His analysis explains why case-marked subjects cannot occur in infinitival clauses, although NPs can be projected up to an infinitival clause's specifier position. Stowell considers the following examples to be small clauses and constituents.
What does and does not qualify as a small clause varies in the literature: the example sentences in (8) contain (what some theories of syntax judge to be) small clauses.[9] In each example, the posited small clause is in boldface, and the underlined expression functions as a predicate over the nominal immediately to its left, which is the subject. The verbs that license small clauses are a heterogeneous set, and fall into five classes:
8. | contexts for small clauses in English | ||
a. | (i) | Susan considers ['''''Sam <u>a dope</u>''''' ]. | |
(ii) | We want ['''''you <u>sober</u>''''' ]. | ||
b. | (i) | Jim called ['''''me <u>a liar</u>''''' ]. | |
(ii) | They named ['''''him <u>Pedro</u>''''' ]. | ||
c. | (i) | Fred wiped ['''''the table <u>clean</u>''''' ]. | |
(ii) | Larry pounded ['''''the nail <u>flat</u>''''' ]. | ||
d. | (i) | We saw ['''''Fred <u>leave</u>''''' ]. | |
(ii) | Did you hear ['''''them <u>arrive</u>''''' ]? | ||
e. | (i) | Larry believes ['''''that <u>to be folly</u>''''' ]. | |
(ii) | Do you judge ['''''it <u>to be possible</u>''''' ]? |
A trait that the examples in (8a-b-c) have in common is that the small clause lacks a verb. Indeed, this is sometimes taken as a defining aspect of small clauses, i.e. to qualify as a small clause, a verb must be absent.[10] [11] [12] If, however, one allows a small clause to contain a verb, then the sentences in (8d-e) can also be treated as containing small clauses:[13] The similarity across the sentences (8a-b-c) and (8d-e) is obvious, since the same subject-predicate relationship is present in all these sentences. Hence if one treats sentences (8a-b-c) as containing small clauses, one can also treat sentences (50e-f) as containing small clauses. A defining characteristic of all five contexts for English small clauses in (8a-b-c-d-e) is that the tense associated with finite clauses, which contain a finite verb, is absent.
Broadly speaking, there are three competing analyses of the structure of small clauses.[14]
The flat structure organizes small clause material into two distinct sister constituents.[16]
The a-trees on the left are the phrase structure trees, and the b-trees on the right are the dependency trees. The key aspect of these structures is that the small clause material consists of two separate sister constituents.
The flat analysis is preferred by those working in dependency grammars and representational phrase structure grammars (e.g. Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar and Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar).
The layered structure organizes small clause material into one constituent. The phrase structure trees are again on the left, and the dependency trees on the right. To mark the small clause in the phrase structure trees, the node label SC is used.
The layered analysis is preferred by those working in the Government and Binding framework and its tradition, for examples see Chomsky,[17] Ouhalla, Culicover, Haegeman and Guéron.
See X-Bar Theory for a general exploration of X-Bar Theory.
X-bar theory predicts that a head (X) will project into an intermediate constituent (X') and a maximal projection (XP). There were three common analyses of the internal structure of a small clause under X-Bar theory.[18] Here they are each presented as showing the NP AP small clause complement in the sentence (highlighted in bold), "I consider (NP)Mary (AP)smart":
In this analysis, neither of the constituents determine the category, meaning that it is an exocentric construction. Some linguists believe that the label of this structure can be symmetrically determined by the constituents,[19] [20] and others believe that this structure lacks a label altogether.[21] In order to indicate a predicative relationship between the subject (in this case, the NP Mary), and the predicate (AP smart), some have suggested a system of co-indexation, where the subject must c-command any predicate associated with it.[22]
This analysis is not compatible with X-bar theory because X-bar theory does not allow for headless constituents, additionally this structure may not be an accurate representation of a small clause because it lacks an intermediate functional element that connects the subject with the predicate. Evidence of this element can be seen as an overt realization in a variety of languages such as Welsh, Norwegian, and English, as in the examples below (with the overt predicative functional category highlighted in bold):
Some have taken this as evidence that this structure does not adequately portray the structure of a small clause, and that a better structure must include some intermediate projection that combines the subject and the predicate which would assign a head to the constituent.
In this analysis, the small clause can be identified as a projection of the predicate (in this example, the predicate would be the 'smart' in 'Mary smart'). In this view, the specifier of the structure (in this case, the NP 'Mary') is the subject of the head[23] (in this case, the A 'smart'). This analysis builds on Chomsky's[24] model of phrase structure and is proposed by Stowell[25] and Contreras.[26]
The PrP[27] (predicate phrase) category (also analyzed as AgrP,[28] PredP,[29] and
\pi
Additionally, some have theorized that a combination of the three structures can illustrate why the subjects of verbal small clauses and adjectival small clauses seem to behave differently, as noted by Basilico:[31]
Here, examples (13) and (14) show that the subject of an adjectival small clause — with our without copular be — can raise to the matrix subject position. However, with a verbal clause, omission of infinitival to leads to ungrammatically, as shown by the contrast between the well-formed (15) and the ill-formed (16), where the asterisk (*) marks ungrammaticality. From this evidence, some linguists have theorized that the subjects of adjectival and verbal small clauses must differ in syntactic position. This conclusion is bolstered by the knowledge that verbal and adjectival small clauses differ in their predication forms. While adjectival small clauses involve categorical predication where the predicate ascribes a property to the subject, verbal small clauses involve thetic predications where an event that the subject is participating in is reported. Basilico uses this to argue that a small clause should be analyzed as a Topic Phrase, which is projected from the predicate head (the Topic), with the subject introduced as the specifier of the Topic Phrase.[32] In this way, he argues that in an adjectival small clause, the predicate is formed for an individual topic, and in a verbal small clause the events form a predicate of events for a stage topic, which accounts for why verbal small clauses cannot be raised to the matrix subject position.[33]
A small clause divides into two constituents: the subject and its predicate. While small clauses occur cross-linguistically, different languages have different restrictions on what can and cannot be a well-formed (i.e., grammatical) small clause.[34] Criteria for identifying a small clause include:
A small clause is characterised as having two constituents NP and XP that enter into a predicative relation, but lacking finite tense and/or a verb. Possible predicates in small clauses typically include adjective phrases (AP), prepositional phrases (PPs), noun phrases (NPs), or determiner phrases (DPs) (see determiner phrase page on debate regarding the existence of DPs).
There are two schools of thought regarding NP VP constructions. Some linguists believe that a small clause characteristically lacks a verb, while others believe that a small clause may have a verb but lacks inflected tense. The following examples, which all lack verbs, illustrate small clauses with [NP AP] (17), [NP DP] (18), and [NP PP] (19):
The small clause examples in (17) to (19) contrast with the examples in (20) to (22), with the critical difference being the inclusion of the copular verb be preceded by infinitival to:[1]
In some analyses the presence of the copular verb and tense (infinitival to) makes the bolded portions a full clause rather than a small clause. However, other analyses treat infinitival clauses as a kind of small clause. The latter approach proposes that small clauses lack inflected tense but can have a bare infinitival verb. Under this theory, NP VP constructions are allowed. The following examples contrast small clauses with non-finite verbs with main clauses with finite verbs.
The asterisk here represents that the sentence (24) is generally held to be ungrammatical by native English speakers.
Small clauses satisfy selectional requirements of the verb in the main clause in order to be grammatical.[35]
The argument structure of verbs is satisfied with small clause constructions. The following two examples show how the argument structure of the verb "consider" affects what predicate can be in the small clause.[36]
Example (18) is ungrammatical as the verb "consider" does take an NP complement, but not a PP complement.
However, this theory of selectional requirement is also disputed, as substitution of different small clauses can create grammatical readings. Both examples (28) and (29) take PP complements, yet (28) is grammatical but (29) is not.
The matrix verb's selection of case also supports the theory that the matrix verb's selectional requirements affect small clause licensing. The verb consider in (30) marks accusative case on the subject NP of the small clause. This conclusion is supported by pronoun-substitution, where the accusative caseform is grammatical (31), but the nominative case form is not (32).
In Serbo-Croatian, the verb smatrati 'to consider' selects for accusative case for its subject argument and instrumental case as its complement argument.[38]
(33) | (Ja) | smatram | ga | budalom. | |
I-NOM | consider | him-ACC | a fool-INSTR | ||
'I consider him a fool.' |
(34) * | (Ja) | smatram | ga |
| |
I-NOM | consider | him-ACC |
| ||
['I consider '''him a fool'''.'] |
Small clauses' grammaticality judgments are affected by their semantic value.
The following examples show how semantic selection also affects predication of a small clause.
Some small clauses that appear to be ungrammatical can be well-formed given the appropriate context. This suggests that the semantic relation of the main verb and the small clause affects sentences' grammaticality.
Small clauses may not be negated by a negative modal or auxiliary verb, such as don't, shan't, or can't.[40] Small clauses may only be negated by negative particles, such as not.
There are a number of considerations that support or refute the one or the other analysis. The layered analysis, which, again, views the small clause as a constituent, is supported by the basic insight that the small clause functions as a single semantic unit, i.e. as a clause consisting of a subject and a predicate.
Only constituents of a like type can be joined via coordination. Small clauses can be coordinated, which suggests they are constituents of a like type, but see coordination (linguistics) on the controversy regarding the effectiveness and accuracy of coordination as a constituency test. The following examples illustrate small clause coordination for [NP AP] (32), and [NP NP/DP] (33) small clauses.
The layered analysis is also supported by the fact that in certain cases, a small clause can function as the subject of the greater clause, e.g.
Most theories of syntax judge subjects to be single constituents, hence the small clauses Bill behind the wheel and Sam drunk here should each be construed as one constituent. Concerning small clauses in subject position, see Culicover, Haegeman and Guéron.
Further, small clauses can appear as the complement of with, e.g.:
These data are also easier to accommodate if the small clause is a constituent.
One could argue, however, that small clauses in subject position and as the complement of with are fundamentally different from small clauses in object position. Some datapoints have the small clause following the matrix verb, whereby the subject of the small clause is also the object of the matrix clause. In such cases, the matrix verb appears to be subcategorizing for its object noun (phrase), which then functions as the subject of the small clause. In this regard, there are a number of observations suggesting that the object/subject noun phrase is a direct dependent of the matrix verb. If so, then this means the flat structure is the correct analysis. This captures that fact, with such object/subject noun phrases, as illustrated in (47), the small clause generally does not behave as a single constituent with respect to movement diagnostics. Thus, the "subject" of a small clause cannot participate in topicalization (47b), clefting (47c), pseudo-cleating (47d), nor can it served as an answer fragment (47e). Moreover, like ordinary object NPs, the "subject" of a small clause can becomes the subject of the corresponding passive sentence (47f), and can be realized as a reflexive pronoun that is coindexed with the matrix subject (47g).
47. Application of movement diagnostics to [NP AP] small clause | |||
a. | She proved him guilty. | ||
b. |
| Small clause fails topicalization diagnostic for identifying constituents. | |
c. |
| Small clause fails clefting diagnostic for identifying constituents. | |
d. |
| Small clause fails pseudoclefting diagnostic for identifying constituents. | |
e. |
| Small clause fails the answer fragment diagnostic for identifying constituents | |
f. | He was proved guilty. | Subject of small clause becomes the subject of matrix clause in the corresponding passive sentence. | |
g. | She1 proved herself1 guilty. | Reflexive pronoun takes the matrix subject as its antecedent. |
The datapoints in (47b-g) are consistent with the flat analysis of small clauses: in such an analysis the object of the matrix clause plays a dual role insofar as it is also the subject of the embedded predicate.
Small clauses' constituency status is not agreed upon by linguists. Some linguists argue that small clauses do not form a constituent, but rather form a noun phrase.
One argument is that [NP AP small] clauses cannot occur in the subject position without modification, as shown by the ungrammatically of (48).[41] However, these [NP AP] small clauses can occur after the verb if they are modified, such as in example (49).
A second argument is coordination tests make incorrect predictions about constituency, particularly regarding small clauses. This casts doubt upon the status of small clauses as constituents.
Another counterexample of constituency looks at depictive secondary predicates.[43]
One school of thought argues that this example has [''the water up''] behaving as a constituent small clause, while another school of thought argues that the verb "sponge" does not select for a small clause, and that the water up semantically, but not syntactically, shows the resultative state of the verb.
Complement small clauses are related to the phenomena of raising-to-object, therefore this theory will be discussed in more detail for English and Korean.
Raising-to-object with a direct object is illustrated in (52) with the verb proved. The bolded constituents represent the small clause of the sentence. By hypothesis, the raising-to-object analysis treats the subject of the small clause as having raised from the embedded small clause to the main clause
52.[44] | ||
a. | The DA proved ['''two men <u>guilty</u>''' ] during each other’s trials | |
b. | The DA proved ['''no suspect <u>guilty</u>''' ] during his trial | |
c. | The DA proved ['''no one <u>guilty</u>''' ] during any of the trials |
Raising (linguistics) is obligatory in small clauses for the make out construction. This is evident by the grammaticality of (i) and ungrammaticality of (ii) without raising-to-object behaviour as demonstrated in the table below:
53. | ||
a. | They're trying to make John out a liar | |
b. |
|
The range of scope can also implicate the subject of Raising in small clauses.[44] Semantically, wide scope entails a general situation, for example, where everyone has some person that they love, whereas narrow scope entails a specific situation, for example, where everyone love the same person.[45] Considering only verbless small clauses, small clauses are only accessibly with the wide range of scope with respect to the main verb.[44]
54. | ||
a. | I believe someone guilty | |
b. | John proved two assumptions false |
In Korean, raising-to-object is optional from with complement clauses, but obligatory with complement small clauses.[46] A fully inflected complement clause is given in (55), and the object Mary can be marked either with nominative case (55a) or with accusative case (55b). In contrast, with a complement small clause as in (56), the subject of the small clause can only be marked with accusative; thus while (56a) is ill-formed, (56b) is well-formed.
55. Korean complement clause: optional raising-to-object | |||||||||
a. | 존 | 은 | 매리 | 가 | 미덥 | -다- | -고 | 생각한다 | |
John | un | Mary | ga | mitep | -ta- | -ko | sangkakhanda | ||
John | NOM | Mary | NOM | reliable | DEC | COMP | think.PRES.DECL | ||
b. | 존 | 은 | 매리 | 를 | 미덥 | -다- | -고 | 생각한다 | |
John | un | Mary | lul | mitep | -ta- | -ko | sangkakhanda | ||
John | NOM | Mary | ACC | reliable | DEC | COMP | think.PRES.DECL | ||
'John thinks that Mary is reliable.' |
56. Korean complement small clause: obligatory raising-to-object | ||||||||
a. | 존 | 은 | 매리 |
| 미덥 | -게 | 생각한다 | |
John | un | Mary |
| mitep | -gye | sangkakhanda | ||
John | NOM | Mary |
| reliable | SC | think.PRES.DECL | ||
b. | 존 | 은 | 매리 | 를 | 미덥 | -게 | 생각한다 | |
John | un | Mary | lul | mitep | -gye | sangkakhanda | ||
John | NOM | Mary | ACC | reliable | SC | think.PRES.DECL | ||
'John thinks Mary reliable.' |
At first glance, French small clauses appear to be unrestricted relative to which category can realize a small clause. Illustrative examples are given below: there are [NP AP] small clauses (57); [NP PP] small clauses (58), as well as [NP VP] small clauses (59).
57. | Louis | considère | [<sub>NP</sub> '''''Marie''''' ] | [<sub>AP</sub> '''<u>''drôle''</u>''' ]. | |
Louis | considers | Marie | funny | ||
'Louis considers Marie funny.'[47] |
58. | Marie | voulait | [<sub>NP</sub> '''''Louis''''' ] | [<sub>PP</sub> '''<u>''dans son bureau''</u>''' ]. | |
Marie | want+past | Louis | in her office | ||
'Marie wanted Louis in her office.' |
59. | Louis | voyait | [<sub>NP</sub> '''''Marie''''' ] | [<sub>VP</sub> '''<u>''jouer de la cornemuse''</u>''' ]. | |
Louis | see+past | Marie | play+inf. of the bagpipe | ||
'Louis saw Marie play the bagpipe.' |
(d) |
| |||||
| crois | Jean | être | malade. | ||
I | believe | Jean | to be | sick. |
(e) | Louis considers (NP)Mary (AP)funny and (NP)Bill (AP)stupid. | |||||||
Louis | considère | [Marie''' |'''drôle] | et | [Bill''' |'''stupide] | ||||
Louis | considers | Marie | funny | and | Bill | stupid |
(f) | Louis gave [a book to Mary yesterday] and [a painting to Barbara the day before]. | ||||||||||||||||
Louis | a | donné | [un''' |'''livre''' |'''à''' |'''Marie''' |'''hier] | et | [une''' |'''peinture''' |'''à''' |'''Barbara''' |'''le''' |'''jour''' |'''d'''' |'''avant]. | ||||||||||||
Louis | have | give+past | [a</u> |<u>book</u> |<u>to</u> |<u>Mary</u> |<u>yesterday] | and | [a</u> |<u>painting</u> |<u>to</u> |<u>Barbara</u> |<u>the</u> |<u>day</u> |<u>of</u> |<u>yesterday</u>.<u>] |
Lithuanian small clauses may occur in a NP NP or NP AP construction. NP PP constructions are not small clauses in Lithuanian as the PP does not enter into a predicative relationship with the NP.[48] The example (a) below is of an NP NP construction. The example (b) below is of an NP AP construction. While the English translation of the sentence includes the auxiliary verb "was", it is not present in Lithuanian.
(a) | Wilson proclaimed (NP)Cagan (NP)a nobleman.[49] | ||||
Wilsonas | paskelbė | Kaganą | bajoru. | ||
Wilson-NOM | proclaimed | Cagan | nobleman. |
(b) | The Supreme Court declared that (NP)the protest (was) (AP)well-founded.[50] | ||||||
Aukščiausias | teismas | pripažino | kad | protestas | pagrįstas | ||
Supreme | Court-NOM | proclaimed | that | protest-NOM | well-formed |
(c) |
| ||||
[Ją''' |'''nesubrendusia''' |'''mergiote] | jis | laiko. | |||
[Her-ACC</u> |<u>immature</u> |<u>brat] | he-NOM | considers. |
(d) |
| |||||
| jis | laiko | nesubrendusia | mergiote. | ||
| he-NOM | considers | immature | brat. |
In Mandarin, a small clause does not only lack a verb and tense, but also the presence of functional projections.[53] The reason for this is that the lexical entries for particular nouns in Mandarin not only contain the categorical feature for nouns, but also for verbs. Thus even with the lack of functional projections, nominals can be predicative in a small clause. (a) illustrates a complement small clause: it has no tense-marking, only a DP subject and an NP predicate. However, the semantic difference between Mandarin Chinese and English with regards to its small clauses are represented by example (b) and (c). Though (b) is the embedded small clause in the previous example, it cannot be a matrix clause. Despite having the same sentence structure, a small clause consisting of a DP and an NP, due to the ability of a nominal expression to also belong to a second category of verbs, example (c) is a grammatical sentence. This is evidence that there are more restrictive constraints on what is considered a small clause in Mandarin Chinese, which requires further research.
a. I consider him a student. | |||||
我 | 当 | 他 | 学生 | ||
Wǒ | dāng | tā | xuéshēng | ||
I | consider | him | student |
b. He is a student. | |||
| 学生 | ||
| xuéshēng | ||
he | student |
c. He is Taiwanese. | ||||
他 | 臺灣 | 人 | ||
tā | taiwan | rén | ||
He | taiwan | -ese |
Below is case of special usage of small clause used with the possessive verb yǒu. The small clause is underlined.
Zhangsan is (at least) as tall as his older brother. | |||||
张三 | 有 | 他 | 哥哥 | 高 | |
Zhāngsān | yŏu | tā | gēgē | gāo | |
Zhangsan | have | his | older brother | tall |
Here, the possessive verb yǒu takes a small clause complement in order to make a degree comparison between the subject and indirect object. Due to the following AP gāo, here the possessive verb yǒu expresses a limit of the degree of tallness. It is only with a small clause complement that this uncommon degree use of the possessive verb can be communicated.[54]
In Brazilian Portuguese, there are two types of small clauses: free small clauses and dependent small clauses.
Dependent small clauses are similar to English in that they consist of an NP XP in a predicative relation. Like many other Romance languages, Brazilian Portuguese has free subject-predicate inversion, although it is restricted here to verbs with single arguments.[55] Dependent small clauses may appear in either a standard, as in example (a), or an inverted form, as in example (b).
(a) | [subject-predicate] order | (b) | inverted [predicate-subject] order | |||||||
Considero | os | meninos | inocentes. | Considero | (AP)inocentes | (NP)os | meninos. | |||
consider-1SG | the-PL | boys | innocent-PL. | consider-1SG | innocent-PL | the-PL | boys. | |||
I consider (NP)the boys (AP)innocent.[56] | I consider (NP)the boys (AP)innocent. |
| [subject-predicate] order | (d) | inverted [predicate-subject] order | ||||||||
(NP)A | sua | casa | (AP)bonita! | (AP)Bonita | (NP)a | sua | casa! | ||||
the | your | house | beautiful | beautiful | the | your | house | ||||
| 'How beautiful your house is | ' |
---|
In Spanish, like many Romance languages, there is some flexibility in small clause construction due to the flexibility in word order. This is posited to be due to the fact that Spanish is an example of a language that is discourse-prominent and agreement-oriented. This passing of features onto the v allows a separation of the object from the verb when the focus of the sentence changes. The final position in a sentence is reserved for the focus as seen by the differences in (a) and (b).
(a) | Juan ate (NP)the meat (AP)raw.[58] | ||||
Juan | comió | la carne | cruda. | ||
Juan | ate | the meat | raw. |
(b) | Juan ate (NP)the meat (AP)raw. | ||||
Juan | comió | cruda | la carne. | ||
Juan | ate | raw | the meat. |
The difference in preference for one construction over the other ([XP NP] versus [NP XP]) is determined by discourse features.[58] Refer to the following two examples. In (c) the establish topic is the XP, AP in this case, meaning the information we are seeking is the NP.
(c) | (NP)Whom do you consider (AP)very clever?. | |||
¿A quién | consideras | muy lista? | ||
to whom | consider-PRES.2.SG | very clever-FEM.SG |
Answer
(d) | I consider Susana (AP)very clever. | ||
(i) | Considero | muy lista | a Susana |
consider-PRES.1SG | very clever-FEM.SG | to Susana | |
(ii)# | Considero | a Susana | muy lista |
consider-PRES.1SG | to Susana | very clever-FEM.SG | |
In the following example (e) the reverse is true. We are given the NP in the question and are seeking the information of the XP.
(e) | How do you consider (NP)Susana?. | |||
¿Cómo | consideras | a Susana? | ||
how | consider-PRES.2.SG | to Susana |
Answer
(f) | I consider Susana (AP)very clever. | ||
(i)# | Considero | muy lista | a Susana |
consider-PRES.1SG | very clever-FEM.SG | to Susana | |
(ii) | Considero | a Susana | muy lista |
consider-PRES.1SG | to Susana | very clever-FEM.SG | |
Notice in (d) and (f) that the English answer remains the same regardless of the question, but in Spanish, one ordering is preferred over the other. When the new information being presented is the XP, the construction preferred is [NP XP]. This is because the sentence-final position is reserved for focus.
It is worth noting that the non-preferred formations (d)(ii) and (f)(i) can be accepted as grammatical if the new information is given the prosodic stress or the established information is destressed, and there is a longer pause between the two constituents, making it right-dislocated.
Greek is another example of a language that is discourse-prominent and agreement-oriented, allowing features to be passed onto the v.[58] This allows for flexibility in word order depending on the changing focus of the small clause. This example can be shown in (a) and (b). The construction can either take [XP NP] or [NP XP] formations with the focused constituent appearing sentence-finally.
(a) | John ate (NP)the meat (AP)raw. | ||||
janis | efaγe | to kreas | omo. | ||
John | ate | the meat | raw. |
(b) | John ate (NP)the meat (AP)raw. | ||||
janis | efaγe | omo | to kreas. | ||
Joan | ate | raw | the meat. |
The difference in preference for one construction over the other is determined by discourse features. Newly given information is considered the focus of the sentence and is therefore preferred in sentence-final position. Refer to examples (c) and (e). In (c) the information we are given is the XP (AP in this case) and the information we are seeking is the DP. This means that the preferred construction is [XP DP]. The reverse is true of example (e).
(c) | (NP)Whom do you consider (AP)very clever?. | |||
pjon | θeoris | poli eksipno? | ||
who-MSC.ACC | consider-2SG | very clever-MSC.SG.ACC |
Answer
(d) | I consider John (AP)very clever. | |||
(i) | θeoris | poli eksipno | to jani | |
consider-PRES.1SG | very clever-MSC.SG.ACC | the John-ACC | ||
(ii)# | θeoris | to jani | poli eksipno | |
consider-PRES.1SG | the John-ACC | very clever-FEM.SG |
(e) | How do you consider (NP)John?. | |||
ti | θeoris | to jani? | ||
what-NEUT.ACC | consider-2SG | the John-ACC |
Answer
(f) | I consider John (AP)very clever. | |||
(i)# | θeoris | poli eksipno | to jani | |
consider-PRES.1SG | very clever-MSC.SG.ACC | the John-ACC | ||
(ii) | θeoris | to jani | poli eksipno | |
consider-PRES.1SG | the John-ACC | very clever-FEM.SG |
It is worth noting that the non-preferred formations (d)(ii) and (f)(i) can be accepted as grammatical if the new information not in sentence-final position is given the emphatic stress.[58]
Expressive Small Clauses, like SCs are verbless and the noun does not carry descriptive content but instead carries expressive content.[59] Expressive Small Clauses are evidence that small clauses learned in early development, last until adulthood for language speakers.[60] ESCs are illustrated in (a). Expressive small clauses are never used in an argument position of the phrase as seen in (b-i) and do not generally occur within the embedded clause of a sentence as seen in (b-ii). Both of the examples below are ungrammatical. The bolded constituents are the ESCs.
(a) | |
Oh, you fool! | |
You idiot! | |
You nincompoop! |
(b) | ||
(i) |
| |
(ii) |
|
Unlike ESCs in English, Japanese ESCs differ in two ways: second person pronouns are not used, and ESCs sometimes appear in argument position. The example below shows a well-formed ESC in Japanese.
(a) | This fool | |||
Ko | -no | baka | ||
This | -no | fool |
The phrase in (a) illustrates the pattern found in Japanese ESCs: [NP<sub>1</sub>''—no—''NP<sub>2</sub>]. (a) illustrates the use of a proximate demonstrative in NP1 position. Additionally, first person pronouns, kinship terms, proper names, and other nouns with a vocative use are able to appear in NP1 position—except for the intermediate demonstrative so (the/that) which is not permitted in ESCs.
(b) | You fool | |||
?? | Anata | no | baka | |
You 2SG | no | fool |
(c) | Hey Yamada, that fool Tanaka made a mistake again. | ||||||||||
Oi | Yamada | Tanaka | no | baka | ga | mata | shippai | -shita | yo | ||
Hey | Yamada | Tanaka | no | fool | NOM | again | mistake | -did | PART |
Because English is agreement-prominent, there is inflexible SC word order and a heavy importance on intonational focus. Though both answers in English use the same words, focus is given by prosodic stress.
(a) | ||
Question | Who do you consider clever? | |
Answer | I consider Susan very clever. |
(b) | ||
Question | How do you consider Susan? | |
Answer | I consider Susan very clever. |
Spanish has a flexible SC word order, and word order determines focus but prosodic stress is able to be used to make non-preferred constructions felicitous. These examples show the non-felicitous construction but they would be accepted by speakers if the underlined constituents are given emphatic stress and precede a long pause.
(c) | ||
Question | Whom do you consider clever? | |
¿A quién consideras muy lista? | ||
Answer | Considero a Susan muy lista | |
consider-PRES.1SG to Susana very clever-FEM.SG | ||
I consider Susan very clever. |
(d) | ||
Question | How do you consider Susana? | |
¿Cómo consideras a Susana? | ||
Answer | Consider muy lista a Susana | |
consider-PRES.1SG very clever-FEM.SG to Susana | ||
|
Language | Intonational Focus | Word Order Flexibility | Expressive Small Clauses | Agreement-prominent | Discourse-prominent | |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
English | ✓ | X | ✓ | ✓ | X | |
French | ||||||
Brazilian Portuguese | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | |||
Spanish | ✓* | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ||
Greek | ✓* | ✓ | ✓ | ✓ | ||
Japanese | ✓ | X | ✓ |