Outer measure explained
In the mathematical field of measure theory, an outer measure or exterior measure is a function defined on all subsets of a given set with values in the extended real numbers satisfying some additional technical conditions. The theory of outer measures was first introduced by Constantin Carathéodory to provide an abstract basis for the theory of measurable sets and countably additive measures. Carathéodory's work on outer measures found many applications in measure-theoretic set theory (outer measures are for example used in the proof of the fundamental Carathéodory's extension theorem), and was used in an essential way by Hausdorff to define a dimension-like metric invariant now called Hausdorff dimension. Outer measures are commonly used in the field of geometric measure theory.
Measures are generalizations of length, area and volume, but are useful for much more abstract and irregular sets than intervals in
or balls in
. One might expect to define a generalized measuring function
on
that fulfills the following requirements:
- Any interval of reals
has measure
- The measuring function
is a non-negative extended real-valued function defined for all subsets of
.
- Translation invariance: For any set
and any real
, the sets
and
have the same measure
of pairwise
disjoint subsets of
It turns out that these requirements are incompatible conditions; see non-measurable set. The purpose of constructing an outer measure on all subsets of
is to pick out a class of subsets (to be called
measurable) in such a way as to satisfy the countable additivity property.
Outer measures
Given a set
let
denote the
collection of all subsets of
including the
empty set
An
outer measure on
is a
set functionsuch that
of
Note that there is no subtlety about infinite summation in this definition. Since the summands are all assumed to be nonnegative, the sequence of partial sums could only diverge by increasing without bound. So the infinite sum appearing in the definition will always be a well-defined element of
If, instead, an outer measure were allowed to take negative values, its definition would have to be modified to take into account the possibility of non-convergent infinite sums.
An alternative and equivalent definition.[1] Some textbooks, such as Halmos (1950) and Folland (1999), instead define an outer measure on
to be a function
such that
and
are subsets of
with
then
of
Proof of equivalence. |
Suppose that
is an outer measure in sense originally given above. If
and
are subsets of
with
then by appealing to the definition with
and
for all
one finds that
The third condition in the alternative definition is immediate from the trivial observation that
Suppose instead that
is an outer measure in the alternative definition. Let
be arbitrary subsets of
and suppose that One then haswith the first inequality following from the second condition in the alternative definition, and the second inequality following from the third condition in the alternative definition. So
is an outer measure in the sense of the original definition. | |
Measurability of sets relative to an outer measure
Let
be a set with an outer measure
One says that a subset
of
is
-measurable (sometimes called
Carathéodory-measurable relative to
, after the
mathematician Carathéodory) if and only if
for every subset
of
Informally, this says that a
-measurable subset is one which may be used as a building block, breaking any other subset apart into pieces (namely, the piece which is inside of the measurable set together with the piece which is outside of the measurable set). In terms of the motivation for measure theory, one would expect that
area, for example, should be an outer measure on the plane. One might then expect that every subset of the plane would be deemed "measurable," following the expected principle that
whenever
and
are disjoint subsets of the plane. However, the formal logical development of the theory shows that the situation is more complicated. A formal implication of the
axiom of choice is that for any definition of area as an outer measure which includes as a special case the standard formula for the area of a rectangle, there must be subsets of the plane which fail to be measurable. In particular, the above "expected principle" is false, provided that one accepts the axiom of choice.
The measure space associated to an outer measure
It is straightforward to use the above definition of
-measurability to see that
is
-measurable then its
complement
is also
-measurable.The following condition is known as the "countable
additivity of
on measurable subsets."
are
-measurable pairwise-disjoint (
for
) subsets of
, then one has
Proof of countable additivity. |
One automatically has the conclusion in the form "
" from the definition of outer measure. So it is only necessary to prove the "
" inequality. One has for any positive number
due to the second condition in the "alternative definition" of outer measure given above. Suppose (inductively) that Applying the above definition of
-measurability with
and with
one has which closes the induction. Going back to the first line of the proof, one then has for any positive integer
One can then send
to infinity to get the required "
" inequality. | |
A similar proof shows that:
are
-measurable subsets of
then the union
and intersection
are also
-measurable.
The properties given here can be summarized by the following terminology:One thus has a measure space structure on
arising naturally from the specification of an outer measure on
This measure space has the additional property of
completeness, which is contained in the following statement:
such that
is
-measurable.This is easy to prove by using the second property in the "alternative definition" of outer measure.
Restriction and pushforward of an outer measure
Let
be an outer measure on the set
.
Pushforward
Given another set
and a map
define
f\sharp\mu:2Y\to[0,infty]
by
One can verify directly from the definitions that
is an outer measure on
.
Restriction
Let be a subset of . Define by
One can check directly from the definitions that is another outer measure on .
Measurability of sets relative to a pushforward or restriction
If a subset of is -measurable, then it is also -measurable for any subset of .
Given a map and a subset of, if is -measurable then is -measurable. More generally, is -measurable if and only if is -measurable for every subset of .
Regular outer measures
Definition of a regular outer measure
Given a set, an outer measure on is said to be regular if any subset
can be approximated 'from the outside' by -measurable sets. Formally, this is requiring either of the following equivalent conditions:
\mu(A)=inf\{\mu(B)\midA\subseteqB,Bisμ-measurable\}
- There exists a -measurable subset of which contains and such that
.It is automatic that the second condition implies the first; the first implies the second by taking the countable intersection of
with
The regular outer measure associated to an outer measure
Given an outer measure on a set, define by
\nu(A)=inf\{\mu(B):\mu-measurablesubsetsB\subsetXwithB\supsetA\}.
Then is a regular outer measure on which assigns the same measure as to all -measurable subsets of . Every -measurable subset is also -measurable, and every -measurable subset of finite -measure is also -measurable.
So the measure space associated to may have a larger σ-algebra than the measure space associated to . The restrictions of and to the smaller σ-algebra are identical. The elements of the larger σ-algebra which are not contained in the smaller σ-algebra have infinite -measure and finite -measure.
From this perspective, may be regarded as an extension of .
Outer measure and topology
Suppose is a metric space and an outer measure on . If has the property that
\varphi(E\cupF)=\varphi(E)+\varphi(F)
whenever
d(E,F)=inf\{d(x,y):x\inE,y\inF\}>0,
then is called a metric outer measure.
Theorem. If is a metric outer measure on, then every Borel subset of is -measurable. (The Borel sets of are the elements of the smallest -algebra generated by the open sets.)
Construction of outer measures
See also: Valuation (measure theory).
There are several procedures for constructing outer measures on a set. The classic Munroe reference below describes two particularly useful ones which are referred to as Method I and Method II.
Method I
Let be a set, a family of subsets of which contains the empty set and a non-negative extended real valued function on which vanishes on the empty set.
Theorem. Suppose the family and the function are as above and define
\varphi(E)=infl\{
p(Ai)|E\subseteqcup
Ai,\foralli\inN,Ai\inCr\}.
That is, the infimum extends over all sequences of elements of which cover, with the convention that the infimum is infinite if no such sequence exists. Then is an outer measure on .
Method II
The second technique is more suitable for constructing outer measures on metric spaces, since it yields metric outer measures. Suppose is a metric space. As above is a family of subsets of which contains the empty set and a non-negative extended real valued function on which vanishes on the empty set. For each, let
C\delta=\{A\inC:\operatorname{diam}(A)\leq\delta\}
and
\varphi\delta(E)=infl\{
p(Ai)|E\subseteqcup
Ai,\foralli\inN,Ai\inC\deltar\}.
Obviously, when since the infimum is taken over a smaller class as decreases. Thus
\lim\delta\varphi\delta(E)=\varphi0(E)\in[0,infty]
exists (possibly infinite).
Theorem. is a metric outer measure on .
This is the construction used in the definition of Hausdorff measures for a metric space.
See also
References
- Book: Gerald B... Folland. Real Analysis: Modern Techniques and Their Applications. 2nd. John Wiley & Sons. 1999. 0-471-31716-0.
- Book: C.D.. Aliprantis. K.C.. Border. Infinite Dimensional Analysis. 3rd. Springer Verlag. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York. 2006. 3-540-29586-0.
- Book: Carathéodory, C.. Constantin Carathéodory
. Constantin Carathéodory. Vorlesungen über reelle Funktionen. 3rd. 1918. 1968. German. Chelsea Publishing. 978-0828400381.
- Book: Evans . Lawrence C. . Gariepy . Ronald F. . Measure theory and fine properties of functions. Revised edition. . Textbooks in Mathematics . CRC Press, Boca Raton, FL . 2015 . xiv+299 . 978-1-4822-4238-6.
- Book: Federer, H.. Herbert Federer
. Geometric Measure Theory. Classics in Mathematics. 1st ed reprint. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York. 1969. 1996. 978-3540606567. Springer Verlag. Herbert Federer.
. Paul Halmos. Measure theory. Springer Verlag. Berlin, Heidelberg, New York. Graduate Texts in Mathematics. 1978. 978-0387900889. 2nd. 1950.
External links
Notes and References
- The original definition given above follows the widely cited texts of Federer and of Evans and Gariepy. Note that both of these books use non-standard terminology in defining a "measure" to be what is here called an "outer measure."