Consequentia mirabilis (Latin for "admirable consequence"), also known as Clavius's Law, is used in traditional and classical logic to establish the truth of a proposition from the inconsistency of its negation.[1] It is thus related to reductio ad absurdum, but it can prove a proposition using just its own negation and the concept of consistency. For a more concrete formulation, it states that if a proposition is a consequence of its negation, then it is true, for consistency. In formal notation:
(\negA\toA)\toA
Weaker variants of the principle are provable in minimal logic, but the full principle itself is not provable even in intuitionistic logic.
Consequentia mirabilis was a pattern of argument popular in 17th-century Europe that first appeared in a fragment of Aristotle's Protrepticus: "If we ought to philosophise, then we ought to philosophise; and if we ought not to philosophise, then we ought to philosophise (i.e. in order to justify this view); in any case, therefore, we ought to philosophise."[2]
Barnes claims in passing that the term consequentia mirabilis refers only to the inference of the proposition from the inconsistency of its negation, and that the term Lex Clavia (or Clavius' Law) refers to the inference of the proposition's negation from the inconsistency of the proposition.[3]
The following shows what weak forms of the law still holds in minimal logic, which lacks both excluded middle and the principle of explosion.
Frege's theorem states
(B → (C\toD))\to((B → C)\to(B\toD))
D=\bot
B=C
(B → \negB) → \negB
B=\negA
(\negA\to\neg\negA)\to\neg\negA
(\negA\to\neg\negA)\leftrightarrow\neg\negA
(\negA\toA)\to\neg\negA
\neg\negA\leftrightarrowA
This shows that already minimal logic validates that a proposition
A
A
\negA
\neg\negA
The weak form
(\negA\toA)\to\neg(\negA)
\neg(A\land\negA)
\neg((\negA\toA)\land(\negA))
(B\to\negC)\leftrightarrow\neg(B\landC)
The negation of any excluded middle disjunction
B\lor\negB
\negB
B\lor\negB
The following argument shows that the converse also holds. A principle related to case analysis may be formulated as such: If both
B
C
A
A
((B\toA)\land(C\toA)\land(B\lorC))\toA
B=A
C=\negA
((\negA\toA)\land(A\lor\negA))\toA
A\lor\negA
One has that
(A\toB)\toA
(A\toB)\to(A\landB)
(\negA\toA)\leftrightarrow(\negA\to(A\land\bot))
\neg\negA
In intuitionistical logic, the principle of explosion itself may be formulated as
\bot\to(A\land\bot)
\bot\leftrightarrow(A\land\bot)
(\negA\toA)\leftrightarrow\neg\negA
It was established how consequentia mirabilis follows from double-negation elimination in minimal logic, and how it is equivalent to excluded middle. Two more classical arguments follow.
When excluded middle holds for
A
(B\toA)\to(A\lor\negB)
B=\negA
Related to the last intuitionistic derivation given above, consequentia mirabilis also follow as the special case of Pierce's law
((A\toB)\toA)\toA
B=\bot