Axiom of extensionality explained
The axiom of extensionality,[1] [2] also called the axiom of extent,[3] [4] is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory.[5] [6] The axiom defines what a set is. Informally, the axiom means that the two sets A and B are equal if and only if A and B have the same members.
In ZF set theory
In the formal language of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms, the axiom reads:
\forallx\forally[\forallz(\left.z\inx\right.\leftrightarrow\left.z\iny\right.) → x=y]
[7] [8] [9] or in words:
If the sets
and
have the same members, then they are the same set.
In, all members of sets are themselves sets, but not in set theory with urelements. The axiom's usefulness can be seen from the fact that, if one accepts that
\existsA\forallx(x\inA\iff\Phi(x))
, where
is a set and
is a formula that
occurs free in but
doesn't, then the axiom assures that there is a unique set
whose members are precisely whatever objects (urelements or sets, as the case may be) satisfy the formula
.The converse of the axiom,
\forallx\forally[x=y → \forallz(\left.z\inx\right.\leftrightarrow\left.z\iny\right.)]
, follows from the substitution property of
equality. Despite this, the axiom is sometimes given directly as a
biconditional, i.e., as
\forallx\forally[\forallz(\left.z\inx\right.\leftrightarrow\left.z\iny\right.)\leftrightarrowx=y]
.
In NF set theory
Quine's New Foundations (NF) set theory, in Quine's original presentations of it, treats the symbol
for equality or identity as shorthand either for "if a set contains the left side of the equals sign as a member, then it also contains the right side of the equals sign as a member" (as defined in 1937), or for "an object is an element of the set on the left side of the equals sign if, and only if, it is also an element of the set on the right side of the equals sign" (as defined in 1951). That is,
is treated as shorthand either for
\forallz\left.(x\inz\right. → \left.y\inz\right.)
, as in the original 1937 paper, or for
\forallz\left.(z\inx\right.\leftrightarrow\left.z\iny\right.)
, as in Quine's
Mathematical Logic (1951). The second version of the definition is exactly equivalent to the
antecedent of the ZF axiom of extensionality, and the first version of the definition is still very similar to it. By contrast, however, the ZF set theory takes the symbol
for identity or equality as a primitive symbol of the formal language, and defines the axiom of extensionality in terms of it. (In this paragraph, the statements of both versions of the definition were paraphrases, and quotation marks were only used to set the statements apart.)
In Quine's New Foundations for Mathematical Logic (1937), the original paper of NF, the name "principle of extensionality" is given to the postulate P1,
((x\subsety)\supset((y\subsetx)\supset(x=y)))
,
[10] which, for readability, may be restated as
x\subsety → (y\subsetx → x=y)
. The definition D8, which defines the symbol
for identity or equality, defines
as shorthand for
(\gamma)(\left.(\alpha\in\gamma\right.)\supset(\left.\beta\in\gamma\right.))
. In his
Mathematical Logic (1951), having already developed
quasi-quotation, Quine defines
\ulcorner\zeta=η\urcorner
as shorthand for
\ulcorner(\alpha)(\left.\alpha\in\zeta\right. .\equiv.\left.\alpha\inη\right.)\urcorner
(definition D10), and does not define an axiom or principle "of extensionality" at all.
[11] Thomas Forster, however, ignores these fine distinctions, and considers NF to accept the axiom of extensionality in its ZF form.
In ZU set theory
In the Scott–Potter (ZU) set theory, the "extensionality principle"
(\forallx)(\left.x\ina\right.\Leftrightarrow\left.x\inb\right.) ⇒ a=b
is given as a theorem rather than an axiom, which is proved from the definition of a "collection".
[12] In set theory with ur-elements
An ur-element is a member of a set that is not itself a set.In the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms, there are no ur-elements, but they are included in some alternative axiomatisations of set theory.Ur-elements can be treated as a different logical type from sets; in this case,
makes no sense if
is an ur-element, so the axiom of extensionality simply applies only to sets.
Alternatively, in untyped logic, we can require
to be false whenever
is an ur-element.In this case, the usual axiom of extensionality would then imply that every ur-element is equal to the
empty set.To avoid this consequence, we can modify the axiom of extensionality to apply only to nonempty sets, so that it reads:
\forallA\forallB(\existsX(X\inA)\implies[\forallY(Y\inA\iffY\inB)\impliesA=B]).
That is:
Given any set A and any set B, if A is a nonempty set (that is, if there exists a member X of A), then if A and B have precisely the same members, then they are equal.
Yet another alternative in untyped logic is to define
itself to be the only element of
whenever
is an ur-element. While this approach can serve to preserve the axiom of extensionality, the
axiom of regularity will need an adjustment instead.
See also
References
- Paul Halmos, Naive set theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. (Springer-Verlag edition).
- Jech, Thomas, 2003. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer. .
- Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. Elsevier. .
Notes
Notes and References
- Web site: AxiomaticSetTheory . 2024-08-20 . www.cs.yale.edu.
- Web site: Naive Set Theory . 2024-08-20 . sites.pitt.edu.
- Book: Bourbaki, N. . Theory of Sets . 2013-12-01 . Springer Science & Business Media . 978-3-642-59309-3 . 67 . en.
- Book: Deskins, W. E. . Abstract Algebra . 2012-05-24 . Courier Corporation . 978-0-486-15846-4 . 2 . en.
- Web site: Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory . 2024-08-20 . www.cs.odu.edu.
- Web site: Intro to Axiomatic (ZF) Set Theory . 2024-08-20 . www.andrew.cmu.edu.
- Web site: Set Theory > Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory (ZF) (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) . 2024-11-24 . plato.stanford.edu . en.
- Web site: Zermelo-Fraenkel Set Theory . 2024-11-24 . www.cs.odu.edu.
- Web site: Naive Set Theory . 2024-11-24 . sites.pitt.edu.
- Quine . W. V. . 1937 . New Foundations for Mathematical Logic . The American Mathematical Monthly . 44 . 2 . 74, 77 . 10.2307/2300564 . 0002-9890.
- Quine . W. V. . 1951-12-31 . Mathematical Logic . DeGruyter . 134-136 . 10.4159/9780674042469.
- Book: Potter, Michael D. . Set theory and its philosophy: a critical introduction . 2004 . Oxford University Press . 978-0-19-926973-0 . Oxford ; New York . 31 . ocm53392572.